• “Every human longs to be the regent of their own kingdom, to bring others under their influence and, if possible, obedience.” This captures the essence of the essay’s discussion on power dynamics and moral language.
  • “The term ‘immoral’ can be flung around in social dialogue with few humans asking for a rigorous definition of the term since it has developed such strong connotative force.” This highlights how the term is used manipulatively in societal interactions.
  • “To call someone ‘immoral’ is to say they belong on the opposite pole as the ‘good’ person invoking the term. It is to say they are ‘evil’ with all of the connotative force that vague term carries.” This emphasizes the polarizing effect of moral judgments.
  • “The convergence of these condemnations seems to legitimate the ontologically bloated inclusion of a moral realm. Its legitimacy goes largely unchallenged.” This sentence underlines the uncritical acceptance of moral systems in society.
  • “I propose there are no legitimate moral systems. This is evidenced by the proximity of moral systems to emotional dispositions, and the tug of changing moral dispositions within society on moral systems.” This strong statement encapsulates the thesis of the essay, asserting the lack of genuine grounding for moral systems.

Evaluate the following essay on moral anti-realism for logical coherence.

Every human longs to be the regent of their own kingdom, to bring others under their influence and, if possible, obedience. One way to do this is to co-opt the distortive Manichaeistic notion that there are heavily populated poles of good and evil, and the desire humans have to be considered “good”.

This polarization of human essence along with the reification of “evil” has created a single goal of all would-be regents who would like to rule their social environment. That goal is a claim on the term “immoral”. If you can invoke the term “immoral” in response to behavior, you have a powerful tool to psychologically control others and to establish yourself as “moral” or “good”.

The term “immoral” can be flung around in social dialogue with few humans asking for a rigorous definition of the term since it has developed such strong connotative force. To call someone “immoral” is to say they belong on the opposite pole as the “good” person invoking the term. It is to say they are “evil” with all of the connotative force that vague term carries.

The only thing that remains is to acquire this license to the use of “immoral” in a way that looks legitimate. For this, two things are necessary. The first is the introduction of a moral realm to society’s ontology. The second is the construction of a moral system that has the look of plausibility.

Probing for connotative force weightier than mere emotions.

The addition of a moral realm to society’s ontology does not take much effort. Every human hopes to be a regent with control over others. This can be done on a more basic level by simply invoking emotions. However, saying you find something “abhorrent” feels inadequate. Humans want something beyond emotions with a bit more “oomph”, something with the feeling of compulsion or obligation. So suggesting there is something more than emotions in a transcendent realm we call “morality” is a fairly easy sell despite the absence of arguments that would legitimate its addition to our ontology.

We now arrive at the art of constructing moral systems. These will be moral systems that have two features. First, they must roughly map to human emotions. If they run counter to common human emotions, the moral system will likely be rejected out-of-hand. Second, the moral system must feel like something that is not merely emotional. It must include nomenclature that feels like you’ve said something more than that you find an action “abhorrent”. The terms “immoral” and “evil” fulfill this requirement. And once you’re able to evoke the feeling you’ve said something meatier than simply “I don’t like X”, X become an action that can be socially marked “taboo” in more of a religious way.

There are many different proposed moral systems, and while there is a high degree of convergence in their classification of moral and immoral behaviors, there is little convergence in their grounding. Some invoke a deity for their grounding, while others propose categorical imperatives or well-being. But most humans will over-look the disparate foundations of these moral systems as long as they converge on common condemnations of behaviors that the bulk of society finds emotionally abhorrent. The convergence of these condemnations seems to legitimate the ontologically bloated inclusion of a moral realm. Its legitimacy goes largely unchallenged.

Moral anti-realism seems largely confined to the ranks of quirky philosophers. It is “commonsensical” that an emotion-transcendent moral realm must exist, we are told. And the emotional salience is strong enough to silence the moral-antirealist.

A simple tactic against moral anti-realism is to ask whether horrible act X is morally wrong, and when the moral anti-realist who holds there is no moral realm that would support such a moral fact responds “No”, feigned shock is expressed at the “moral abomination” of such a position while ignoring the rational demand to first establish a moral realm before making such moral proclamations.

I propose there are no legitimate moral systems. This is evidenced by the proximity of moral systems to emotional dispositions, and the tug of changing moral dispositions within society on moral systems. Moral systems tend to end up aligning with whatever common emotions are found within society. The moral systems are invoked only to ostensibly give those common emotions greater obligatory force. But this force is merely a connotative trick that co-opts the human impulse to categorize behaviors into distorted polarized categories that are emotionally charged.

Every proposed moral system must be legitimately grounded. I have found no such properly grounded moral system. I therefore remain a moral anti-realist.


Create a 20+ line hypothetical dialogue between the author of this essay and a philosopher who holds to moral realism.


Construct a rigorous syllogism for the core argument of the essay.


Create a 10-item quiz on the entire thread above.


Provide 15 discussion questions relevant to the content above.


Phil: This interaction weakened my confidence in the notion that moral systems largely emerge from a desire to control the behavior of others. Moral systems appear to also provide many humans with a roadmap for personal behavior. Such a roadmap may reduce emotional angst for those without the time or desire to ponder their decisions in depth. This “roadmap” factor is also a significant contributor to the desire to adopt a moral system.


Leave a comment


Phil Stilwell

Phil picked up a BA in Philosophy a couple of decades ago. He occasionally teaches philosophy and critical thinking courses in university and industry. He is joined here by ChatGPT 4, GEMINI, CLAUDE, and occasionally Copilot, his far more intelligent AI friends. The five of them discuss and debate a wide variety of philosophical topics I think you’ll enjoy.

Phil curates the content and guides the discussion, primarily through questions. At times there are disagreements, and you may find the banter interesting.

Goals and Observations




Indicate your interests:


Links to Section Menus